The following are lecture notes from a talk I gave at Campbell Law School on Jan. 23, 2015
I. Professionalism
and the ABA Report, "On the Future of Legal Education"
You might recall the ABA Report on the Future of Legal Education came out last January (2014), which has largely
been seen as a call to make “practice ready” lawyers. It describes the consensus view among its authors about the purpose of legal education among this way:
“Provide legal and related services in a professionally
responsible fashion.”
But, what does “professionally responsible” mean in this context? Surely, it means more than that the lawyers do not violate the rules of professional responsibility. What more could it mean?
In her book, The Majesty of Law, Justice Sandra Day O’Connor addresses the professional identity of the lawyer:
One distinguishing feature of any profession, unlike other occupations that may be equally respectable, is that membership in a profession entails an ethical obligation to temper one’s selfish pursuit of economic success [even though that obligation cannot] be enforced either by legal fiat or through the discipline of the market.... Both the special privileges incident to membership in the profession and the advantage those privileges give in the necessary task of earning a living are means to a goal that transcends the accumulation of wealth. That goal is public service.
But, this dimension of the lawyer’s education gets scant attention in the Report., which speaks of a fundamental tension between:
· Public values, described as the values effecting the “competence, availability, and professionalism.” (NOTE that professionalism is not defined, but a professional responsibility class is mentioned).
· Private value, knowledge, skills, and credentials.
Education for public service, as Justice O’Connor describes it, is not a value that the Report considers explicitly.
Neither Justice O’Connor nor Markowitz suggest what moral values ought to be taught to lawyers or why it matters that they have them, other than to have some personal sense of coherence and esteem.
------------------- [35:34 to 42:07] -------------------------- [1:13:30 to 1:16:40] ------
What can we make of this meeting? What went wrong here that some of the best legal minds of the time were incapable of realizing the moral meaning of what they were doing?
Elizabeth Mertz’s book, The Language of Law School, suggests the pedagogical problem: In essence, her argument is that law professors do a very good job of teaching legal reasoning. They do this in part by forcing 1Ls to set aside the moral discourse of ordinary language, in order to acquire the grammar and syntax of the legal profession. Their normal moral understanding is truncated—the depth of moral understanding is shallower. In short, to train them as lawyers we make them banal in Arendt’s terms. They come to know the reasoning of the law, but at the cost suppressing their moral intuitions.
IV. Why Jurisprudence?
Jurisprudence courses can provide particularly rich opportunities for such engagement. The reason for this the that the subject matter of jurisprudence is the nature of law itself. One of the central questions of jurisprudence (or Legal Theory, to use the more etymologically correct term) is the correct understanding of the relationship between law and moral norms. That is to say, legal theory has always been an investigation into the moral meaning of law. It has always looked beyond the formalities of legal reasoning and inquired about the nature of legal interpretation.
Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, in his famous address at Boston University, published under the name, The Paths of the Law, puts prediction as first among the goals of legal analysis. What goes into predicting a legal outcome? Analysis of the formal legal rules, yes. But more than that. The legal Realists rightly pointed out that Legal Formalism—the desire to reduce the fullness of legal thought to the operation of formal legal principles, leaves the law open to exploitation by the socially dominant groups. Formalism, the Realists observed, provided the legal justification for social Darwinism, and ultimately the death camps of the Nazis. The thinking out of thought, as Arendt would say, led to a banal analysis of law that enabled the lawyers of Wanasee to lawfully order mass executions. The banality of evil is shallow thoughtlessness.
It is worth noting here that the eugenics act that enabled the death camps had its origins here in Raleigh at the Eugenic center that existed only a block from this building. And despite the fact that the German drafter was sentenced to die by the Nuremburg Tribunal, the North Carolina drafter, who was decorated by Adolf Hitler, did not receive punishment; the North Carolina Eugenics Board remained in operation until 1977. And the Eugenics Act was not repealed until 2003.
These devices are coming, and they will change the economics of law practice. They will not replace human beings, but they will steal away the jobs that are fit only for shallow legal thinkers. The routine and route forms of legal reasoning will have little value in the marketplace because they can be automated.
Since jurisprudence classes explore what is distinctly human, what cannot be reduced to an algorithmic operation, the provide students with an opportunity for critical thinking about the tools of legal analysis that they have recently acquired. Understanding this is also a fundamental benefit to students from studying jurisprudence. In the practice lives of our students, they will see incredible change to the society and to their practice. The will need to be more creative and innovative, more adaptable, more flexible in their understanding. In short, they will need to have abstract understanding of law in order to think through the changes they will encounter. Jurisprudence will help them with that too.
To close, let me offer a plea for enriching the student with a fine appreciation of legal theory. The hallmark of professionalism is to understand the nature of the professional services that one provides, to have broad and even wise perspectives on how and when and what to achieve with the technical skills and techniques of lawyering. To be professional is to have autonomy and moral integrity. To be a professional is to think deeply and understanding the meaning of one’s acts. To be able to assess the changes in legal practice, to respond to social change with moral integrity and a purposive plan for future action.
No comments:
Post a Comment